Causation and models of disease in epidemiology

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2009.09.006Get rights and content

Abstract

Nineteenth-century medical advances were entwined with a conceptual innovation: the idea that many cases of disease which were previously thought to have diverse causes could be explained by the action of a single kind of cause, for example a certain bacterial or parasitic infestation. The focus of modern epidemiology, however, is on chronic non-communicable diseases, which frequently do not seem to be attributable to any single causal factor. This paper is an effort to resolve the resulting tension. The paper criticises the monocausal model of disease, so successful in the nineteenth century. It also argues that a multifactorial model of disease can only be satisfactory if it amounts to more than a mere rejection of the monocausal model. A third alternative, the contrastive model, is proposed and defended on the grounds that it links the notions of disease and of general explanation, while avoiding the philosophical naiveties and practical difficulties of the monocausal model.

Introduction

Two conceptual questions currently face epidemiology, both relating to causation. First, how should it handle certain diseases, which appear to be etiologically more complex than the infections and deficiencies by which epidemiology made its name? In particular, chronic non-communicable diseases (CNCDs) account for a larger proportion of deaths, at least in the industrialised world, than they did in 1900 (Rockett, 1999, p. 8), and attract more epidemiological attention. Yet they often do not seem susceptible to definition in terms of any one causative agent: their etiology is typically complex.

Second, how should epidemiology respond to newly identified causes of disease? Epidemiology has moved beyond obvious environmental causes of illness (such as prolonged extreme cold) and uncovered increasingly complex and sometimes surprising environmental causes of disease. And in place of the old notion of a ‘constitution’, the discipline has had to grapple with a newly discovered category of cause: genetics. The increased depth and complexity of our knowledge of both genetic and environmental determinants of health places pressure on aspects of the conceptual framework of epidemiology: in particular, on the way it thinks about disease causation.

Devising a conceptual framework for thinking about disease causation has proved astonishingly difficult. On the one hand, the early history of epidemiology appears to attest to the power of insisting that every disease has one cause that is necessary and, in limited circumstances, sufficient for the disease. I call this way of thinking about disease etiology the monocausal model of disease. This model suits infectious diseases such as TB and cholera well, along with parasitic infestations and diseases of deficiency. On the other hand, the monocausal model is a terrible fit for CNCDs such as lung cancer or diabetes. It is theoretically possible that a condition like diabetes has a single necessary and, in some circumstances, sufficient cause, which we have not yet discovered. But surely, it is also a theoretical possibility that there is no cause for diabetes satisfying that description. And even if there is, it is not clear how insisting that there must be such a cause helps us achieve public health or clinical goals, if we don’t know what it is. The causes that we are able to identify are causal risk factors: neither necessary nor sufficient. These are all we have to work with. Accordingly, a view of disease as multifactorial now dominates epidemiology. But this is not an entirely happy situation, because it fails to mark what looks like a real etiological difference between diseases like cholera and conditions like lung cancer. The monocausal model has had some striking successes in the history of epidemiology, and these successes are left unexplained by the mere assertion that disease causation is multifactorial. Unless we can explain the successes of the monocausal model in terms of modern multifactorial thinking, there is a risk of throwing the baby out with the bathwater.

In this paper I want to address the tension that arises between monocausal and multifactorial models of disease. Both are, to some extent, rational reconstructions of positions that are implicit in the epidemiological literature. There have been very few (if any) attempts to lay out these two ways of thinking about disease causation, in a fully explicit and philosophically rigorous manner. Accordingly there is a danger of attacking straw men. It should be understood that these models of disease, as I state them, are attempts to make explicit ways of thinking that are implicit: so I refrain from attributing the result of this exercise as an opinion of any historical or contemporary figure. Nevertheless, I do think—and will argue—that these ways of thinking are present in various extant efforts to conceptualise disease causation. Once I have assessed the strengths and weaknesses of these two models of disease, I will propose a ‘contrastive’ model, which attempts to preserve the strengths of the monocausal model within a multifactorial framework.

Section snippets

The monocausal model

Perhaps the closest medicine has come to an explicit statement of the monocausal model of disease is Koch’s postulates. However, contrary to the impression sometimes conveyed, even these postulates have no authoritative statement. Koch’s own work does not define the postulates authoritatively (see Evans, 1993, Ch. 2, for several versions and discussion). Moreover, the postulates are shot through with practical concerns; they do not constitute a philosophical model of disease. This reflects the

Problems for the monocausal model

Even if successes can be claimed for it, the monocausal model as I have sketched it suffers from a number of objections. Starting with the most obvious, the monocausal model provides no justification for its restriction on the number of causes by which a disease may be defined. Why should there not be states of ill health where two, or a hundred and one, kinds of cause are used for classification? To take a simple example, swine influenza as it occurs naturally is caused by the synergistic

Multifactorial approaches

Until the latter part of the nineteenth century, medical text books contained lengthy lists of causes for any given condition. Effort was sometimes made to distinguish immediate causes from remote, or to make some other distinction of this sort; but it was nevertheless standard to find a great many different causes listed in the etiology of a single condition, and also to find a number of repeat offenders among the causes of a great many different diseases (Carter, 2003, Ch. 1). Various kinds

A contrastive model

In Section 3 I listed some problems for the monocausal model of disease, and in Section 4 I argued that a multifactorial approach is also unsatisfactory if it consists in merely rejecting the monocausal model of disease. Accordingly, in this section I shall tentatively propose a more positive multifactorial approach.

The most obvious shortcoming of the monocausal model of disease concerned its restriction of the number of causes (of a certain sort) that a disease may have. Often it seems helpful

Objections

The most obvious shortcoming of the contrastive model I have proposed is that it leaves a crucial component unspecified: it does not tell us anything about the contrast class, and especially about the notion of health. This is one reason that the proposed conditions are necessary but not jointly sufficient. Perhaps it is an exaggeration to call this a model of disease until this gap has been plugged. But my proposal is no worse that the monocausal or multifactorial models in this respect, since

Acknowledgements

I am especially grateful to Ron Zimmern, who first drew my attention to this area. I would also like to thank Sorin Bangu, Richard Barnett, Jonathan Birch, Adam Bostanci, Kevin Brosnan, Vanessa Heggie, Hai Hong, Stephen John, Luis Nacul, Sridhar Venkatapuram, Caroline Wright, Caitlin Wylie, two anonymous referees, and audiences at the Brocher Foundation conference on the Science and Politics of Neglected Disease Research, and in the Department of History and Philosophy of Science at Cambridge,

References (42)

  • N. Krieger

    Epidemiology and the web of causation: Has anybody seen the spider?

    Social Science and Medicine

    (1994)
  • M. Marmot

    Health in an unequal world: Social circumstances, biology, and disease

    Clinical Medicine

    (2006)
  • Angel, K. (2008). Causality and psychosomatic histories in contemporary Anglo-American biomedicine. Ph.D. thesis,...
  • Beebee, H. (2004). Causing and nothingness. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals...
  • C. Boorse

    On the distinction between disease and illness

    Philosophy of Public Affairs

    (1975)
  • A. Broadbent

    The difference between cause and condition

    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society

    (2008)
  • K.C. Carter

    Childbed fever: A scientific biography of Ignaz Semmelweis

    (1994)
  • K.C. Carter

    The rise of causal concepts of disease

    (2003)
  • Deveraux, P. (2008). Effects of extended release metoprolol succinate in patients undergoing non-cardiac surgery (POISE...
  • R. Doll et al.

    The causes of cancer

    (1981)
  • Ducasse, C. (1926). On the nature and the observability of the causal relation. The Journal of Philosophy, 23(3),...
  • A.S. Evans

    Causation and disease: A chronological journey

    (1993)
  • Hall, N. (2004). Causation and the price of transitivity. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and...
  • Hart, H., & Honoré, A. (1985). Causation in the law (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon...
  • C. Hempel

    The philosophy of natural science

    (1966)
  • J. Henle

    Medicinische Wissenschaft und Empirie

    Zeitschrift fur rationelle Medizin

    (1844)
  • A.B. Hill

    The environment and disease: Association or causation?

    Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine

    (1965)
  • Hotez, P. J., & Daar, A. S. (2008). The CNCDs and the NTDs: Blurring the lines dividing communicable and...
  • Humber, J. M., & Almeder, R. F. (Eds.). (1997). What is disease? Biomedical Ethics Reviews. Totowa, NJ: Humana Press...
  • E. Kingma

    What is it to be healthy?

    Analysis

    (2007)
  • R. Koch

    Verfrahen sur Untersuchung zur conserviren und photographie der Bakterien, Beitrag der Pflanzen

    (1876)
  • Cited by (69)

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text